Nicola Giocoli does not like our review of the book Illiberal Reformers by Thomas Leonard that appeared in the Autumn
issue of the Journal of Economic
Literature. He writes “S&W’s review is so off target, so obviously biased,
so clearly incapable to grasp the book’s true argument that I felt compelled to
write what follows.” We feel similarly.
The essence of
Giocoli’s critique is that we misunderstand and mischaracterize Illiberal Reformers as being an attack
on progressive policy preferences, rather than what it is—an attack on the
progressive predilection for scientism that threatens to subsume popular will
and interest under a misguided elite-driven agenda. The most egregious and
noteworthy example of this, qua Leonard, was the progressive embrace of
eugenics as a policy in itself and as a mindset that informed other policies
premised on excluding undesirable elements from the economy and imposing
corporatist management techniques on the few benighted souls who remain.
If Leonard’s book
really were an indictment of elite scientism, it would be a much more
interesting and valuable work than it is—though not, we hasten to add, a
particularly original one. Among other things, it would address that eugenics
was embraced by the intellectual elite of both left and right, for reasons that
corresponded to their prior ideological commitments—a point we make in our
review. It would also properly characterize where Francis Amasa Walker’s work
in government went wrong—not by imposing his collectivist agenda on an
unwilling public or by ensuring continual high-status employment for his fellow
professional economists, which is how Leonard critiques him, but rather by
altering public statistics so as to influence public opinion in a moderate
direction and avoid inflaming and validating more radical critiques of the
status quo. Such a book certainly would not mischaracterize a New Republic
editorial against the Supreme Court of the “Lochner Era” as an attack on the
Bill of Rights, as Leonard also does, and as Giocoli repeats and echoes in his
piece. All of these are examples out of which you really could construct a
critique of scientific elitism as it actually exists and existed in the
Progressive Era, rather than weaponize such a critique and then wield it
against a contemporary political and intellectual interest you dislike and seek
to discredit.
One of the stranger
aspects of Leonard’s book is the long intellectual history of progressive
economic thought that he constructs out of thin air, linking their writings
about the labor market to the hierarchical vision of society laid out by Plato.
Indeed, the intellectual historian Mary Furner characterized Leonard’s account
as “a hurried and imprecise gloss on the history of labor as work for others,
oddly keyed to the practices of Ancient Greece and based on only two sources
for the U.S. from its beginning to the Gilded Age.” But thanks to Giocoli’s
exegesis of the book, it is finally clear to us what is really going on with
Leonard’s otherwise-mysterious references to ancient Greece. The progressives
saw themselves as just that: progressive, with a vision of society as evolving
upwardly to a higher plain and their own work as constitutive of that progress.
If he can carry the point that ‘actually, the progressives were interested in
resurrecting an ancient, hierarchical social order,’ then the inherent contradictions
in elite progressive scientism are laid bare. So Leonard embarks upon that
project, notwithstanding that the ancient antecedents Leonard finds for
progressive social thought were nowhere acknowledged by the progressives or
their opponents or any other intellectual historian. As we wrote in our review,
that is not good intellectual history. Nor is Leonard’s strange and
suspiciously pat periodization of American economic, political, and
intellectual history—but again, we repeat ourselves.
Moreover, Giocoli
takes us to task for eliding the progressive economists of the late 19th
and early 20th century with the “institutionalist” school of
economics that only took shape during and just after World War I. In fact, we
make clear that there is not an identity between the two, and we elucidate the
views of both John Bates Clark and Francis Amasa Walker, whom Giocoli accuses
us of mischaracterizing. But here Giocoli is referring to the periodization of the
history of institutionalist economics propounded by Malcolm Rutherford in his
excellent book The Institutionalist
Movement in American Economics, 1918-1947, and it’s worth noting that the
one place in which eugenics and similar issues appear in that volume is a
single footnote about John Commons and Edward Ross at Wisconsin (pg. 200 of the
paperback edition, 2013). And well beyond specialized studies of the history of
economic thought, of the literally thousands of words that we have read by the progressive
activists who were ‘in the trenches’ in the press, in the courts, legislatures,
and in churches fighting against palpable abuses of human rights, the word
“eugenics” with its implications of sterilization appears rarely if at all in
them.
The progressives, as
our essay acknowledges, were racists, in some cases imperialists, frequently
immigration restrictionists, as were most public figures of the era. This is
not a secret that Leonard has unveiled. In our article we point to sharp
critiques of these positions in both historical and economic journals. But the
portrayal of them as condescending elitists teaching the poor what was good for
them—an “amalgam of compassion and contempt” according to Leonard (p. xiii)
--is false and derogatory. If we are to
speak of condescension what should we think of the “liberals” of the 1860s and
1870s like E.L. Godkin who recognized the distress of the working classes, but
insisted that the government must in no way assist them directly because it
would breed habits of idleness and dependence?
Giocoli’s piece is
quite revealing, especially in its conclusion—and in that sense, it is also
helpful in reconstructing the whole alternative intellectual history of
economics, in which Leonard’s book and lifetime’s scholarship play a crucial
part, as evidence from the broad and reverential treatment of it found in
history-of-economics curricula developed by overtly ideologically motivated interests. That alternative history is rendered necessary for those interests
by the most recent developments in the field, and is thus inherently,
inescapably anachronistic and not to be trusted. Since it’s crucial to making
sense of what Leonard’s project is, we quote Giocoli’s closing paragraph in
full:
The implication is
that the problems of contemporary economics most recently uncovered by the
great financial crisis are not just theoretical or methodological. They do not
simply consist of the demonstrably wrong foundations of the neoclassical
paradigm, with its unwarranted focus on equilibrium and rationality. Or of the
still relatively underdeveloped status of behavioral and experimental economics.
What Leonard story entails is that the discipline’s biggest problems lie
deeper. They involve the idea itself of the value of economic expertise and the
(im)possibility in social science to go beyond what Hayek dubbed “pattern predictions”
(Hayek 1967). They call into question the intrinsic limits of economic science
qua science, rather than as mere art à la John Neville Keynes (Keynes 1891). Or
the implicit contradiction underlying view that economists’ usefulness stems
from their ability to behave as competent “plumbers” (Duflo 2017) while at the
same time arguing that their “plumbing technology” is both so sophisticated to
make it inaccessible to anyone else (including real “plumbers”, like field
workers) and so basic to make the economists’ involvement wholly dispensable
(viz., everybody passing Econ101 can be a “plumber”). Alas, Illiberal Reformers invites – indeed, compels – caution on the
scientific legitimacy of any government intervention grounded on economic
expertise and, therefore, skepticism on the true value of the giant industry of
economic consulting that the economists’ “pretense of knowledge” has helped
build since the early 20th century. No surprise, then, that self-appointed
master plumbers at the AEA disliked the book.
The situation is
this: in recent years, originating over a decade before the financial crisis of
2008-2009 but accelerating in strength and influence since, economics has been
undergoing an empirical revolution. An aggressive, but to our mind justified,
reading of the result of that revolution would say that it has brought into
serious question the real-world inferences about how the economy works and the
policy recommendations that result therefrom historically associated with an
elite academic economics consensus that prevailed since the postwar
neoclassical revolution. Giocoli himself refers obliquely to it in his
conclusion. There’s no need here to rehash the many subfields and policy
questions in which this has played out—we do so in our review and elsewhere. The point is that this is deeply
threatening to those scholars and outside interested parties strongly
associated with the ideology of that neoclassical revolution.
Their response,
Giocoli makes plain, is to flip the accusation made by proponents of this
empirical revolution around: it is they, the contemporary empiricists who claim
a greater and greater intellectual territory won in battle against a retreating
foe, who suffer from hubris and whose claims to scientific advance ought to be
read in the harsh light of progressive economists’ problematic record. If, for example,
the financial crisis showed that deregulation of the financial sector was a
risky and unwarranted policy premised on simplistic theoretical notions of how
agents act in financial markets and how efficiently those markets allocate
resources, the guilty parties are not the neoclassical scholars who advocated
loosening regulation of financial markets and institutions, but rather the
scientistic mindset that imbued those scholars with the hubris to advocate any
policy at all, and the fault for *that* lies with the progressives, not with
the neoclassicals who were merely wrong about how the economy works, not
anywhere near as damning a sin as scientistic hubris. Indeed, other writings by neoclassically-oriented public
intellectuals offer a similar critique of contemporary empirical scholarship:
empirical work is hard, uncertain, and messy, whereas neoclassical theorizing
tends to be neat and bountiful in hard policy conclusions—provided one doesn’t
let reality get in the way. Wouldn’t it be easier—more scientific, even—for
economists to stick to what we know, the old saws of neoclassical dogma, than
promote and cultivate and skepticism about them in the public mind by undertaking
empirical investigations that might draw them into question, or even just
reveal the extent to which economists are in fact uncertain regarding the field
in which they claim expertise?
This mindset and the
intellectual architecture supporting it—namely, Leonard’s book, as interpreted
by Giocoli—are frankly anti-intellectual and offensive to anyone who values
economics as a would-be social science rather than a religious creed. And it’s
also distastefully hypocritical, because while the charge of excessive hubris
and the innate assumption that what we say ought to be heard by the world and
incorporated into decision making on matters of great public interest could be fairly
said to plague economists of all ideological stripes, at every stage of the
discipline’s history, the inclination to draw strong policy conclusions on the
basis of not a lot of substance has been strongest among the neoclassicals,
entirely willing to argue directly from theoretical models to their policy
implications without stopping along the way for the crucial step of finding out
whether those models were actually true. And that is far more hubristic than
strong claims about what in economics can be established empirically.
Take a subfield and
policy area like antitrust, in which we share Giocoli’s interest and have
learned from his excellent scholarship. The “Chicago School” had an enormous
influence on the reinterpretation of what the antitrust laws of the United
States prohibit. That influence is contained in landmark judicial rulings and
the records of the federal and state agencies empowered to enforce the law. Those
rulings are notably heavy on statements that purport to be about the world,
without a lot of evidence to back them up. The Supreme Court’s dictum in the
case Matsushita v. Zenith Radio Corp.,
which radically heightened the burden on an antitrust plaintiff to prove
anti-competitive behavior to survive summary judgment, was “predatory pricing schemes
are rarely tried and even more rarely successful.” This is a statement about
the world, and yet it contained not a whiff of a citation to any empirical
study estimating the frequency with which predatory pricing is undertaken.
Rather, it is premised on the correctness of a certain economic theory that
holds that it would be irrational and costly for predatory pricing to exist,
therefore it must not exist, and our work here (setting economic policy) is
done.
Robert Bork’s
enormously influential book The Antitrust
Paradox has a similar lack of concern with whether anything he says is
actually true—his assertion that the economy works a certain way is considered
by himself and his adoring fan base on the Supreme Court and (at least in the
past) in the federal antitrust agencies to be sufficient—because, in part, the
way he says the economy works is the way they want it to work in order to
justify the policy conclusions they’ve arrived at ex ante. Again, like
Leonard’s book, that is not scholarship—notwithstanding awards from august
professional organizations and a bountiful stream of worshipful citations from
people with fancy academic job titles and lifetime judicial appointments.
Given that record of
confident—hubristic, even—and enormously influential policy statements made
over many decades by economists and their admirers with a different ideological
orientation than the progressives, it is hard to listen to those same people
and their intellectual heirs adopt a pose of humility—as a weapon engineered
for the counterattack!—as the edifice they built within the profession and
outside it appears to have started to crumble. They aren’t even saying “we
should be, or should have been, more humble.” They are saying “you should be more humble,” and that is
not a very humble thing to say.
Giocoli accuses us
of siding with the elite of the economics profession—and specifically, of the
American Economics Association, in one of its leading journals—and allowing
ourselves to be used as part of its effort to stave off Leonard’s devastating
critique of their high prestige and large influence over policy. According to
Giocoli, we (apparently he means we) are the AEA’s “self-appointed master
plumbers.” That we would have been engaged to carry water for the economics
establishment might strike some of our other readers as an amusing accusation
to level, but we are happy to associate ourselves with the view that it really
is possible for economics to succeed as an empirical social science. The
economy is complex, but it is also amenable to human understanding, and that
scientific advance is premised on testing and rejecting theories, including
ones that many economists themselves heartily wished were true. In fact, that
principle ought to be the real test for who is or is not an economist, not any
ideological commitment. And yet a substantial number of those calling
themselves economists pretend that the greater scholarly principle at stake is
*not* to investigate the truth about how the economy works, however messy it
might be, but rather to adhere mindlessly to received wisdom and to repeat it ad infinitum to interested policy-makers—and
somehow that is supposed to be humble? No thank you.
Finally, to return
to Leonard: Giocoli evidently thinks Illiberal
Reformers is a valuable and original contribution to the intellectual
history of the social sciences, but the core insight it brings to the table,
according to Giocoli, is in fact not original to Leonard. In our review we cite
many historians of progressivism who subjected the movement, especially its
elite intellectual contingent, to a searching treatment, most recently Adam
Cohen in his book Imbeciles. What’s
original in Leonard is his elaborate gloss on progressive motivations and the
connections between their ideology and their cardinal sin of scientism, and
that gloss is just not accurate and is in fact motivated by his own prior
ideological commitments and the current imperatives that result therefrom. Giocoli
accuses us ad hominem of converting Leonard into a political hack writing a
diatribe against the sustained attack on progressivism that has been going on
for years, and makes his own position clear when he says that the charge is a
calumny meant to sustain and justify the attack “on the so-called New Gilded
Age in which American society allegedly lives today.” We cannot help wondering on what planet
Giocoli has been living since the 1980, or if he believes that the absolutely
demonstrable growth of inequality and its attendant harms is a fiction. Neither of us discounts Prof. Leonard’s
expertise nor his sincerity in advancing his ideas or his right to do so. But they are indisputably part of ongoing
attacks on Progressivism with which we disagree and we stated our objections
fairly and debatably in the article itself.
We feel no less strongly about the merits of our position than do
Leonard and Giocoli, whose intimations about the “dark heart of Progressivism”
or the role of “populist agitators” show little respect for the courtesies of
professional argument.
Thus,
notwithstanding the high accolades the book received from Leonard’s own peers,
we rest comfortably with the treatment we gave it in the JEL, and while it
might irk Giocoli that we, whom he evidently does not consider his peers, were
asked to review the book, that editorial decision appears to have been a wise
one in retrospect.